One of the drags on the ability of Spain's economy to recover from the financial crisis of 2007-2009 was the lack of a mechanism for consumers to obtain relief from the debts they ran up in the years leading up to the crisis, debts that were mainly incurred in the form of residential mortgages incurred in the housing boom that paralleled the trajectory of the US's housing boom in those years.
As Spain had no meaningful procedure for individuals to obtain debt relief, it had no method to free up post-crisis wages and salaries from the legacy debt of pre-crisis mortgage debt. This not only dampened overall demand but had the secondary effect of weighing down the Spanish financial system, in a manner very similar to the Japanese banking system a generation earlier, with "zombie" loans, that were neither collectible in accordance with their terms, nor dischargeable, and not susceptible to robust valuation as they lingered on financial institution's balance sheets, given the uncertainty surrounding the prospects for ultimate recovery.
Slowly, Spain's government, led by the center-right Partido Popular that replaced the Socialist coalition that governed into the crisis era, has instituted measures to facilitate consumer debt relief for the first time. There have also been business insolvency reforms, which I am not going to touch on here (for those interested, here are links to some rather spirited memos by Latham and Dentons on those reforms; with regard to the Dentons memo, please be forewarned that there is an egregious mis-translation -- the word "quitas" in Spanish means "discharge," not "pay-off" (you see why I used the word "egregious?)). It's unlikely that there will be very many English-language explanations of Spain's consumer bankruptcy law, which took effect at the end of July, so this seems like an area I can add some value with a post.
Spain's new consumer bankruptcy law -- which is generally referred to as "la ley de segunda oportunidad", or "the law of a second chance" and also applies to small businesses (less than five million euros of debt) -- bears a number of rough resemblances to the US consumer bankruptcy regime, for better or worse. For example, among the eligibility requirements, there is a stringent "good faith" requirement as well as a requirement not to have availed oneself of the procedure within a prescribed period of years.
In general, as one firm of lawyers explains here, the consumer insolvency procedure is basically erected on top of the pre-existing procedural structure for insolvent businesses in Spain to consumers. As with larger business reorganizations, the individual or small business debtor is encouraged to commence a "concurso" outside of court, which, that firm indicates, can last a long time and requires the debtor to "wait patiently". An administrator is appointed and s/he prepares a report. There are negotiations. If there are disputes over how the debtor is conducting his, her or its affairs, there can be resort to a judge. And, as the firm says there are "large etceteras" in that process. If, when all is said and done, there is debt remaining after reaching the requisite threshold of agreement with the creditors, the debtor can ask the court to discharge it.
Or, the individual / small business debtor can take a slightly different path, submitting his or her affairs to a notary (individual debtor) or insolvency mediator (small business) who then is expected to facilitate a similar accord among the creditors.
But, if these corporate insolvency analogues fail, there are two other paths to a discharge for the individual or small business. First, a debtor who, through a judicial proceeding a) liquidates his or her assets, (b) pays in full all of what we would call administrative and statutory priority claims and secured creditors, and c) delivers immediately at least a 25% dividend to unsecured creditors, is entitled to a discharge at that point and need not make further payments out of future income. Second, a debtor who cannot obtain an agreement with creditors and also cannot meet the necessary payment thresholds for immediate discharge, can get a discharge at the end of, and subject to either full compliance or a "strong effort" to comply with, an approved 5-year payment plan (note also that, should the debtor experience a material, favorable change in circumstances during the term of the payment plan, the creditors may ask for more payments). It was not clear to me whether the debtor in the latter case must liquidate assets. The preface to the statute makes a very big deal about the fundamental importance of requiring the debtor to liquidate assets. But, in the case of a small business debtor, liquidating assets seems quite at odds with the goal of servicing a debt repayment plan over 5 years. But, in any case, these two options are roughly similar to our chapters 7 and 13, although stricter in, among other respects, the sense that Spain effectively reverses the US "means test" choosing to route debtors of lesser means into their version of chapter 13. This blogger asserts that the law is still too creditor-friendly, pointing particularly to the ability of creditors to extract more from the debtor during the payment period if circumstances improve materially.
Mortgages are handled in one of three ways. First, the mortgagor can, of course, keep servicing the mortgage. Second, the mortgagor can cede the property to the lender and then any deficiency runs through the process above (except, as I read the commentary on the law, the deficiency cannot be discharged nonconsensually through the 5-year payment plan method). Third, depending on a large number of eligibility criteria, the value of the house, the amount of the annual mortgage payments and the proportion of the mortgagor's annual income that those payments represent, and several "special vulnerability" criteria, the mortgagor is eligible for a procedure that is formally outside of the insolvency laws, known as the "Code of Good Practice" a mortgage restructuring protocol that Spanish banks have adopted "voluntarily" (in the sense of, it's always better to settle with the regulators than to find out what they will do if you don't). There is a hierarchy of debt relief steps that the lenders are supposed to afford the mortgagor under the Code, beginning with lowering the interest rate and stretching out the amortization, and for more difficult debt burdens, write-offs of various magnitudes. Overall, this strikes me as reasonably similar on the big-picture level, to the US approach, with the Code of Good Practices being analogous to HAMP and similar out-of-court protocols in the US. One thing I could not tell was whether the 10% haircut that Spain now imposes on secured claims in corporate insolvencies exists in this consumer context as well.
I couldn't find anything in over half a dozen sources I read regarding exemptions. Most references to liquidation of the debtor's assets described it in plenary terms suggesting to me that exemptions are insubstantial. Certainly there does not appear to be any "homestead exemption".
Although not quite as debtor-friendly as the US consumer bankruptcy regime, and probably too encrusted, even at birth, with substantive complexities and procedural inefficiencies, the "Law of Second Chances" is a big step forward conceptually for Spain and likely to have some positive effect on its economy, which, for unrelated reasons, has finally begun to grow at a normal pace.
Some of the posts on this blog will be completely unnecessary, yet highly proper. Some will be terribly necessary, yet not the least bit proper. Some will hopefully manage to combine the best of the two previous categories. I hope you will find at least one of these categories interesting and enjoyable.
Friday, August 14, 2015
Friday, August 7, 2015
Overstating "White Privilege"
The phrase "white privilege" has become a
standard buzzword among social justice warriors in the United States and creeps
from time to time into more mainstream fora, such as the (poorly argued) debate between Bill O'Reilly and Jon Stewart on The Daily Show last October.
In the New York Times a couple weeks ago, I read a
Michiko Kakutani review
of a new book by Ta-Nehisi Coates, a writer at The
Atlantic whose column I used to read occasionally. The
review summarizes Coates' book as "a searing meditation [sic (I have no
idea how a meditation can "sear"
anything)] on what it means to be black in America today. It takes the form of
a letter from Mr. Coates to his 14-year-old son, Samori, and speaks of the
perils of living in a country where unarmed black men and boys ... are dying at the hands of police officers, an
America where just last month nine black worshipers were shot and killed in a
Charleston, S.C., church by a young white man with apparent links to white
supremacist groups online."
Other MSM participants and, of course, the left wing
echo chamber have dwelt on Coates' book at length too. Like Kakutani's review, David
Brooks of the Times calls it a "searing contribution
to ... education for white people" before excerpting several hateful
passages (example: "‘White America’ is a syndicate
arrayed to protect its exclusive power to dominate and control our
bodies." Or the passage in which he calls the first responders who died in
the 9/11 attacks "menaces of nature")(Parenthetically, I can actually understand someone black feeling that way in the flash of a given moment, but I can't understand anyone retaining that feeling and publishing it after any sort of minimal reflection on the facts of 9/11).
Kakutani's review excerpts a brief passage in which
Coates makes typical assertions about
the benefit of being white in America, which even the review - in the Times! -
characterizes as "cliched".
Notwithstanding that judgment, I want to go beyond epithets into a deeper
analysis of the illogic and inaccuracies in assertions like Coates' about "white privilege", as I did earlier
this year in reaction to a fallacious editorial by Nicholas
Kristof about modern bias experiments.
Here is the excerpt from Kakutani's review:
"Mr. Coates contrasts [the] world of the
streets with the 'other world' of suburbia, 'organized around pot roasts,
blueberry pies, fireworks, ice cream sundaes, immaculate bathrooms, and small
toy trucks that were loosed in wooded backyards with streams and glens.' He
associates this clichéd suburban idyll with ... an exclusionary white dream
rooted in a history of subjugation and privilege. [White people] he contends, 'have forgotten
the scale of theft that enriched them in slavery; the terror that allowed them,
for a century, to pilfer the vote; the segregationist policy that gave them
their suburbs.'"
It's obvious to any reader that white people in
suburbs have no monopoly on pot roasts, blueberry pies, fireworks, ice cream
sundaes, clean bathrooms or small toy trucks.
So, obviously overstated, but that is not my paramount concern, since
any reader can make that judgment for herself or himself. More significant are the examples of
"subjugation and privilege": slavery; vote deprivation; and
segregation. What I want to unpack here
is the confusion between "subjugation" and "privilege",
which the author, and evidently the reviewer, seem to think of as two sides of
the same coin.
I think that is fallacious; that is, probably
because discussion of racial bias tends to proceed in terms of dualities:
white/black; slave/free, etc., which, unquantified, sound equal, reciprocal,
zero-sum, the frame obscures a simple quantitative fact, that the percentage of
blacks in America at relevant times to the discussion has been consistently 10
- 11%, so small that blacks could indeed be "subjugated" by what
Coates identifies, without that subjugation playing a substantial role in
causing the status of very many white people today. Put another way, as I shall illustrate below,
there have been so many more white people in America than black at all relevant
times, that the current economic status of white people is largely independent
of the causes of the current economic status of black people. Therefore, the concept of "white
privilege" is grossly overstated; it would be more accurate to speak about
"disparate impact" of policies on black people than to falsely inflate
the benefit of "white privilege".
An easy demonstration of this is the "segregationist
policies that gave [white people] the suburbs" according to Coates. In the period of most rapid suburban
expansion, 1950 - 1970, there were three censuses and, in each of them, whites never
made up less than 88% of the population:
Year
|
White
|
Black
|
Ratio
|
1970
|
177.7
|
22.6
|
7.9:1
|
1960
|
158.4
|
18.9
|
8.4:1
|
1950
|
134.9
|
15
|
9:1
|
Net
Population Growth
|
31.8%
|
50.7%
|
1.6:1
|
source: Bureau
of the Census, Historical Statistics of the United States, Colonial Times to
1970 (Bicentennial Edition, Part I), Series A73-81; all numbers in millions and
rounded to first decimal
Before I delve more deeply into the demographic
profile of suburban presence in this period, I will offer a simple example of
what these overall demographics mean for "white privilege".
Imagine that every neighborhood in the nation at
these points in time had been a microcosm of the national demographics,
perfectly mirroring the nation's demographics, with no racial disparity
whatsoever. If, for example, there was a
suburban development built in 1950 with 50 homes, the ownership of those homes
would have been allocated 45 to whites and 5 to blacks. By 1970, ownership would have shifted 44:6 (7.9/8.9
* 50).
If we contrast that with the worst-case segregation scenario,
with all the suburbs being populated in the year of highest black population
and yet complete exclusion of the black minority, we see that 6 blacks would
have been excluded, and 6 whites would have benefited disproportionately. But,
88% of whites would have been there
anyway!
This is the simple point that needs to be understood
about "white privilege". The
vast majority of whites would have been in suburbia under any scenario from the
worst case to the most utopian, enjoying all the benefits of the "cliched
suburban idyll" Coates depicts.
They would have seen the same home appreciation; paid the same mortgage
and property taxes; the vast majority of their kids would have gone to the same
public school funded by those taxes, gotten the same grades, and gone to the same colleges; they would have shopped in the same
places, joined the same country club, had much the same social interactions,
etc. Whatever specific example of the "white privilege" argument one
wants to offer, the odds are very high that, as to any given white person, the
identified benefit has not been received at the expense of a black person. Some
white people will have benefited disproportionately but, by definition, even in
the worst case I've just posited, they cannot amount to more that the black
minority's on-average 11% share of the
total population -- and when one delves into the demographics of residence
during the period of suburban expansion more closely, it's really even smaller
than that, more like 3% of white people in the relevant period,
When you get into the demographics of suburban
expansion, you may be surprised to find that the black population in every category classifiable
as suburban grew slightly faster than
the similarly classifiable white population in this time;
Year
|
White
Urban Fringe
|
Black
Urban Fringe
|
White
Rural Nonfarm
|
Black
Rural Nonfarm
|
White
Other Urban
|
Black
Other Urban
|
1970
|
51.4
|
2.54
|
41.3
|
3.8
|
27.8
|
2.7
|
1950
|
19.9
|
0.95
|
28.5
|
2.5
|
24.8
|
2.3
|
Growth
|
158%
|
167%
|
44%
|
52%
|
12%
|
17%
|
source: same
document, Series A73-90; all numbers in millions
However, given that the total black population grew
60% faster than the total white population in those decades, as the first table
showed, these slight differences cover less than half of the black population
growth (3.3 million out of 7.6 million) in those decades. The real change in black population location
was that black rural families moved disproportionately into the central cities, as documented in, among other things, "The Warmth of Other Suns", a 2010 history of that migration by Isabel Wilkerson that won the Pulitzer Prize (such a rural - > urban migration is, by the way, not an uncommon
demographic movement in nations worldwide, regardless of race; it happened in
the Industrial Revolution in England; it has been the source of urbanization in
China and India, for example; it goes on today in Brazil and it is a substantial
part of the Hispanic migration into the US as well).
Year
|
White
Rural
Farm
|
Black
Rural
Farm
|
White
Central Cities
|
Black
Central Cities
|
1970
|
7.8
|
0.45
|
49.5
|
13.1
|
1950
|
19.7
|
3.16
|
42
|
6.1
|
Growth
|
-
60%
|
- 86%
|
18%
|
115%
|
source: same as above
If I recompute the suburban population of 1970 to
mirror the total national population of that year, the racial distribution
would look like this (all numbers in millions):
White
non-farm, non-central-city (unadjusted)
|
White
non-farm, non-central-city (adjusted)
|
Change
|
Black
non-farm, non-central-city (unadjusted)
|
Black
non-farm, non-central-city (adjusted)
|
Change
|
120.1
|
114.6
|
-5.5
|
9.0
|
14.5
|
5.5
|
So, roughly 5.5 million whites would have been
replaced in the suburbs (loosely defined --I know that this national level of analysis is an over-generalization but it is the level Coates argues at, so I think it is where the response should be couched) by blacks, out of a total white suburban population of
120.1 million, or roughly 5%. That same
small shift in the white population would, however, have increased the black
suburban population by roughly 60%.
Measured against the total population of each race in 1970, if you want
to measure the total impact on each race, the numbers are 3.1% and 24%. So that was -- roughly speaking, given the
50,000 foot level of national census data -- the racial disparity in
housing: 96.9% of whites and 76% of
blacks would have landed in the same categories in a racially unaltered allocation of
housing. The point, I hope, is well taken: there is virtually no "white
privilege" in housing (or much of anything else) because whites are such a
large portion of the population, and thus they are inherently a large portion of all of
the outcomes of the population. It's in
fact a ludicrously inaccurate form of stereotyping, as much a stereotype as
claiming that all black men are criminals.
Yet, even if white privilege is in fact negligible, the black population
can experience a disparate negative impact from exclusion. For this reason, it would be more intelligent
to speak in terms of "disparate impact" on blacks than in terms of
the insubstantial "white privilege".
The same proposition holds true when one looks at
income and affluence, instead of housing dispersion. It is of course the case that, on all
statistical fronts, black income is lower than white income. For example, the Census Bureau calculates the
following median incomes for the several main demographic categories in the US
in 2012 as follows (h/t Business
Insider):
"Among the race groups,
Asian households had the highest median income in 2012 ($68,636).
The median income for non-Hispanic White households was $57,009,
and it was $33,321 for Black households. For Hispanic households
the median income was $39,005,"
It seems clear that the same principle holds true,
that, owing to the much larger proportion of white earners in the earning population,
substantially all white people would be in approximately the same position, if
black earners were distributed in perfect proportions throughout the overall
income distribution instead of being over-represented in the lower half of that
distribution and under-represented in the upper half of it. For example, I selected this quote from the
Wikipedia page "Affluence
in the United States" (which, at least as of this date,
has a very progressive perspective):
"in
2005, 81.8% of all 114 million households were White (including White
Hispanics), 12.2% were African American, 10.9% were Hispanic and 3.7% were Asian American. While White
households are always near the national
median due to Whites being the by far most prevalent racial
demographic, the percentages of minority households with incomes exceeding
$100,000 strayed considerably from their percentage of the overall population. Asian Americans, who represent the smallest surveyed racial demographic
in the overall population, were found to be the prevalent minority among six
figure income households. Among the nearly twenty million households with six
figure incomes, 86.9% were White, 5.9% were Asian American, 5.6% were Hispanic; and 5.5% were African American. Among the general individual
population with earnings, 82.1% were White, 12.7% were Hispanic, 11.0% were African American and 4.6% were Asian American."
Note that the percentages add up to > 100%
because of double counting of "white hispanics". Still the order of magnitude of the
white/black ratio is such that the double counting doesn't meaningfully alter
the main point. Even if all "white
hispanics" are subtracted from the "white" population, the
excess percentage of white earners "among the nearly twenty million
households with six figure incomes" is 17% ((.869 - .056) / (.821 - .127)), meaning that 5 of every 6 whites in that top earning bracket would be there if its constituents were a
perfect mirror of the demographics of all earners. That would be the most one could say about
"white privilege" in the modern income distribution (although one
might, I think, fairly question, in an analysis of an asserted birth-based
privilege within the polity of the United States, whether new immigrants,
who (a) were born outside the US and (b) came here voluntarily, should be
weighted; that they dwell in a white majority polity and compete against a white
majority workforce and have to sell to majority white consumers are not
accidents of birth, but the results of their conscious choices. (In fact, one might fairly call it a "privilege"
for a person to be able to live and work in a wealthier polity than the one he
or she was born into). Having been born outside the polity, they are not on an
apples-to-apples basis with the vast majority of the population set being scrutinized;
were they to be subtracted, the white proportion of the population set would
skew higher and the percentage of "excess" white membership in the
top earning bracket would shrink
materially).
A subsidiary point I
want to draw out circles back to my comment at the outset that the Jon Stewart
/ Bill O'Reilly "debate" over "white privilege" was poorly
argued. As I think I've shown, in a
nation that is mostly white, most of the successful people will likely be
white, even in a perfectly racially distributed set of outcomes. So any white person, if challenged to defend
his success against contentions of white privilege, can quite rationally and
legitimately respond by saying, "no, I am confident I would have been in
this position even in a world of perfectly racially distributed outcomes." Obviously some small number of white people
would be wrong in making that statement, but they would be a small
minority. So that is one relevant point
O'Reilly should logically have said in response.
But there is actually
a stronger point that the most successful people like O'Reilly and
Stewart can make. When a white person,
like each of those men, succeeds in generating a very high income, he
has outcompeted, not just the people of color in his demographic cohort, but
the whites in it as well. If he's in the
top 99%, or 99.9%, he's outperformed at least 98% of the other holders of "white
privilege". So mere "whiteness"
can't explain very much of his income, or median white income would be up at
his level. A "white privilege"
attack on the most successful seems to me to be remarkably sophomoric and truly
superficial, even though they are the most visible targets of such
attacks. .
Rather, where the
effects of "white privilege" would be highest would be the lower one goes in the income
distribution. Think of this in terms of displacement. In the very top percentile, let's say, for
argument's sake, 1/6 of the whites are there by virtue of "white
privilege". If you extract them
from the top percentile, they have still outcompeted all the whites below
them. They don't drop to the bottom,
they just drop to the next level of measurement, the 98th percentile; meanwhile,
the people of color from the 98th percentile and lower would hypothetically move up to the
99th to replace them. But this process
repeats at each percentile, and when it does, the proportion of whites that
have to be moved down grows. When you
examine the 98th percentile, because you've just moved whites in from the 99th
percentile, while moving people of color out, it has become even more
lopsidedly white, and therefore, the "1/6 of all whites" in that
cohort is an even larger raw number than in the 99th percentile, so to make it
perfectly racially representative, even more whites within it have to move down
to the 97th percentile, from which even more people of color get moved up again, and
the process snowballs all the way down the income rankings.
What this confirms is
that, at the very top of the income distribution, the whiteness of anyone in
that cohort is least meaningful in terms of its contribution to his or her income,
compared to other positions in the income distribution. Which is really why I thought the O'Reilly /
Stewart "debate" missed the point and was poorly argued.
But, conversely, the
lower one goes in the income rankings, the more likely it becomes that at least
some of the disparity between a white person's income and that of blacks below
them in the rankings can be attributed to the status of being white, because
that white person has outperformed less white people than those above him in
the rankings.
Maybe this explains
in part why "limousine liberals" and other white elites have been
historically more progressive on race, while opposition has tended to be
strongest at the working class level, that intuitively, the former perceive - I
would argue largely correctly - race to have been essentially irrelevant to their success
and therefore they are not really sacrificing any of their status to support
minority progress, while the latter may
intuitively sense their status is more at risk.
Certainly the numbers bear this out.
Coates's passage itemizes other wrongs as well -
slavery and voting discrimination in particular. I am not going to write a tome
on racial issues and civil rights, but I would analyze them with the same
theme, that the black population may suffer a disparate impact from any given
policy, but the outcomes of the white population may not be meaningfully
affected by that policy, and "white privilege" is a terribly
inaccurate frame for the debate. This is
pretty obvious regarding voting, where a 10-11% share of the electorate is not
going to, in and of itself, win any elections, especially were it to be
dispersed proportionally among all neighborhoods (in fact, I wonder whether the
Obama Administration's recently announced plan to push for more racially
distributed housing patterns might ironically wind up diluting black
representation in legislatures over a few decades). Claims of black vote suppression in the 21st century
strike me as a strategic overstatement made for political purposes; the
Democratic party has a huge incentive to maximize black voter presence and
decades of electoral results indicate they have been by and large successful, so
I doubt there remain significant impediments to black votes mattering. In the 2 most recent Presidential elections,
black turnout percentage has surpassed white turnout percentage, which doesn't plausibly reconcile
with a claim of black voter suppression; maybe the candidate matters at the margin (Gore, Kerry, ... Obama).
Slavery has been covered extensively and I have
little to add: all the slaves and slave owners and children thereof and 99%+ of
the grandchildren are dead; the vast majority of the white population did not own
slaves and were so poor they derived negligible benefit from slavery; there
were white slaves and indentured servants throughout the 17th century and
substantial albeit non-slave-level discrimination against certain white ethnic
groups in the 18th and 19th centuries (in my mother's hometown,
when her Irish ancestors arrived, the town experienced "German
flight"); slavery was endemic in Caribbean nations, yet black immigrants
from those nations often outperform African-Americans in the modern US economy;
the Union Army that freed the slaves at staggering human cost to themselves and
their families was almost entirely white; the vast majority of the current
population had no ancestors who profited, even indirectly, from American slavery,
and even among those people who do have such a connection, it represents a
small fraction of their ancestry and personal heritage, so it's myopic and
distorting to focus on that to the exclusion of the rest of their
identity.
Most of the wealth created in
the era of slavery, directly or indirectly, has been destroyed and dissipated,
not just by the Civil War but by the several financial crises and panics since
then, as well as the creative destruction of capitalism at work, not just here
but abroad. Most of the wealth existing
today in the US comes from services provided, goods manufactured and inventions
invented in the post-Jim-Crow era, sure, maybe you can find in some
institution, like a bank or university, that has been around for two hundred
plus years, some record of making money from the slave trade hundreds of years
ago, but that has to be measured against all the money it made from other
sources in its history to gauge the impact of slavery on the status of that institution today.
And a truly full accounting of value transfers between whites and blacks would need
to add in the billions of dollars of transfers, through progressive taxation
and welfare state mechanisms like Medicaid and food stamps, from the
predominantly white upper class to the lowest classes, in which blacks are
disproportionately represented, and the value of the urban infrastructure that "white flight" left behind when the suburban exodus occurred -- the water pipes and reservoirs, electric power plants and wires, sewers, paved roads, and so on -- that the new black arrivals did not have to create from scratch.
I can imagine a number of rejoinders to this
argument. Most of them would, I think,
from having read hundreds of arguments along these lines, be totally ad hominem
and therefore of no intellectual merit; the rejoinders to Brooks's column that
popped up when I googled to find the column, for example, all fall into this
camp. A number would consist of rage and
epithets and personal insults and claims to possess a higher truth by dint of birth that are
again of no intellectual merit.
Some would sophomorically make the "if Bill
Gates were black, he wouldn't have become the richest person in America" argument,
which is (a) fallacious (ecological fallacy), because a statistical analysis, by
definition, does not purport to be true of each and every member of the population
studied (if it were, you wouldn't need a statistical analysis; and in fact you couldn't
do one, as there would be only one statistic); (b) intellectually dishonest, because
it materially changes the data set being studied, and (c) even if the sentence in quotes
were true, the odds are very high that the person who replaces him as "the
richest person in America" would be as white as he is, given the
proportion of whites in the population.
Some would nitpick (e.g.,, blacks are systematically
undercounted in censuses - even so, but not to the extent that the white /
black proportions would change materially, and I know from ancestral research
that whites have been repeatedly
undercounted as well -- among my 8 great-grandparents, for instance, I can come
up with 4 omissions off the top of my head from the censuses of 1910, 1920 and
1930, which is a 16.6% undercounting).
Some would point out, intelligently, that the census
data is insufficiently granular to capture the full extent of housing
segregation -- there are suburbs and then there are suburbs, and even within
suburbs. there was educational segregation (which in my opinion was the largest factor), and everywhere there were job opportunity barriers, often erected by labor unions and politicians responding to their demands (Google "Davis Bacon Act racist" and learn about its racist origins, for instance; why aren't there reparations lawsuits against unions for damages?) True, I agree with all those points. In fact, I would say the root of black economic underperformance lies in the fact that they arrived in urban economies, not only with just rural skills (technical and social), but also, unfortunately, at just the time when the economy was changing over to one that required much more sophisticated skills than even the white working class possessed so their gap was larger and has never closed. But I must also point out that Coates has couched his argument in a simplistic
black-urban / white-suburban duality and I am merely responding apples-to-apples. Were he to write a more nuanced essay, it
would be of greater intellectual merit, but likely not garner him the same
publicity, so he sort of picked his poison and I decline to be judged by a
higher standard than he set for himself. I also note that Coates sharply criticizes education as an answer to black economic status, and is himself a dropout, so again, I am just responding to the man's particular argument, and I think in respect of education he is seriously wrong. As well, education funding has been mainly locally raised and therefore,
if a white community has higher education spending, they're not taking the excess
out of black people's wallets, in some kind of "theft", to use Coates's
word; they're funding it themselves by taxing their own white selves. The progressive argument in this sector is
really the opposite of what Coates is arguing, not that whites are taking from
blacks, but that white income should be taken and spent in majority-minority school
districts by replacing the local property tax method of funding with statewide tax
and transfer mechanisms.
Some would miss the point of this post and assert
that this post whitewashes the harm done to black people from various laws,
which in fact this post recognizes at multiple points; the point of the post is
that contemporary white outcomes are almost entirely independent of contemporary
black status and of policies and actions that harmed black people in the past. Yes, there was segregation, discrimination and racism, and all of that was harmful and wrong, but the demographics are such that the vast majority of white outcomes would have been the same or very close to the same, even if there had been none. That is just a quantitative fact when one population constitutes 88-90% of the total.
The "white privilege" rubric is just a tactical attempt to advance "social justice" by de-legitimizing the success any given white person may have had, and thereby legitimizing the transfer from that person of some of his or her economic gains to minority populations, because, even though the
most successful white people are the ones whose success is least attributable to race, they, as Willie
Sutton once explained about robbing banks, are where the money is.
But it is an intellectually false dogma and deserves to be rebutted by
anyone in the "reality-based community" where I've always prided
myself on dwelling.
Monday, August 3, 2015
Hillary Clinton's Proposal to Combat "Short Term Capitalism" by Raising Capital Gains Tax Rates is Crazy Stupid.
I am stunned at the stupidity of Hillary Clinton's policy
proposal to combat purported "short-term capitalism". I say this as someone who contributed to her
campaign in 2008 and wishes she, not Barack Obama, had been elected President that
year. And my objection does not go to
whether the goal is a good one, which I have views on, but will set to one side
for now. Rather, my objection is, if you
wanted to correct "short-term capitalism", increasing the capital gains tax based on duration of holdings is so obviously
ineffective, I call into question whether anyone with any grasp of stock market
dynamics was involved in formulating the proposal.
1. The Little Guy is Not The Problem. Investors
who pay long-term capital gains taxes are not responsible for most stock
trades. The vast bulk of trading is
done by either (a) tax-exempt institutional investors, like pension funds,
mutual funds, hedge funds, charitable and university endowments, etc. or (b) financial institutions which, while
taxable, change their portfolio daily and already have their profits and losses
taxed as ordinary income, so will not be affected by changes in capital gains rates. Just a small fraction of volume comes from people who pay long-term capital gains taxes. I don't even know if there are any stocks in the S&P
500 as to which non-management, non-institutional holders hold a majority of the outstanding
shares.
2. Compensation Formulas Drive Short-Term Focus. Even when
an asset manager is subject to long-term capital gains taxes on his or her
individual holdings or share of the fund s/he manages, any tax incentive to
hold a position is likely to be offset by the terms of pre-tax compensation, which are generally a function of (a) assets under management (AUM) and (b)
performance (alpha). As well, being able
to show the other investors in the fund a record of above-market performance
enables the manager to retain or attract more funds or reduce any concessions
given in pricing initially. Just to give
a simple example, imagine a $1B fund whose manager owns a rather large 10% of the capital in
the fund; assume it is unleveraged, to simplify things; and has the standard "2%
of AUM & 20% of profit" fee structure. If the manager produces a 20% gain, even if
his or her own share of that gain is taxed at 50%, costing $10 million, that
tax hike is dwarfed by the incremental income received for generating the gain
(2% of the additional $200MM under management is $4MM, while 20% of the $200
million profit is $40 MM, so the manager is up $44 million). Even after you deduct taxes on that income, say
at the same 50% rate, the manager is still way richer for having focused on
short-term performance.
3. Losses? Short-term trading is not limited to selling quickly just to book
a capital gain that gets taxed. Every month, there are stocks
that plunge right after an earnings report or change in guidance. And a good number of the persons selling are
taking a net loss on a position they built up in anticipation of a previously
favorable trend continuing into the future (a/k/a the long term). Think of the people who bought fracking companies just a year ago because U.S. energy independence was a
solid long-term trend. A
capital gains tax hike has absolutely no effect on those trades because they produce no gains, only losses. It may even encourage them, because the
losses they produce can be used to offset short-term gains in other positions. Or, the flip side of the same coin, since the
tax code limits the deductibility of net capital losses, the existence of a
capital loss in one's portfolio can actually cause one to sell another position
that carries a matching gain, so as to soak up the tax benefit of the loss.
4. M&A? To illustrate this, here is an anecdote: I bought shares in a
biotech company earlier this year. Its
drugs in trials had amazing long-term prospects if the trials proved successful, and
I had no monetization event in mind when I bought in. Two months later, a larger company apparently
agreed with my assessment and swooped in and struck an all-cash deal to acquire
the company at about a 50% premium to my purchase price. There was nothing short-term in any buyer's
mind, mine or the acquiror's. Yet the
Clinton proposal would characterize my gain as if it were part of a supposedly
evil short-term investing philosophy.
I would analogize Clinton's proposal to a school that has a
small population of bullies and announces that, to combat their bullying, they will raise
tuition. Or a proposal to curb gasoline
usage by raising the luxury tax on purchasing sports cars. The mismatch between (1) the actors and
actions that precipitate the supposed problem and (2) those who pay the
increased tax is so great, it verges on
the absurd.
If you wanted to curb short-term trading, among the many
better devices would be an excise tax on the aggregate number of trades of less
than the desired duration, or on the aggregate dollar amount of such
trades or on portfolio turnover above a certain level, possibly graduated the further the taxpayer went from the desired norm. That would pick up the institutional holders
who do most of the trading, regardless of their exemption from income taxes,
and it would also capture short-term trades to cut losses. It would also exempt sales in M&A
situations, because those aren't considered trades generally in brokerage
reports. In other words, it would avoid
all of the idiotic pitfalls of the Clinton proposal.
That said, there is a whole roster of macro-level objections
to the proposition that "short-term
capitalism" should be curbed at all, either because it's a net-positive,
or net-neutral, or just not net-very-bad and there are more significant
things to devote political capital to,
all of which I will leave for another day or voice to develop further.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)