In a recent edition
of the invaluable Daily Bankruptcy News, a link appeared to an article by one Professor
Charles Jordan Tabb entitled "The Bankruptcy Clause, the Fifth Amendment
and the Limited Rights of Secured Creditors in Bankruptcy" which dealt
with subjects I find interesting and have written about, so I read it. It turns out to be essentially the same as a
paper he gave at an ABI panel earlier this year, and as that paper is more
accessible, I link to
it rather than the cumbersome SSRN site that DBN linked to.
The article is a good example of two things: One, the traditional law-professor-approach
of taking some appellate opinions, identifying alleged inconsistencies in them,
and then concluding that they really don't mean what people think they mean,
they mean what the professor wants them to mean. The second thing the article exemplifies is
the current vogue of making conclusory claims about deficiencies in corporate
reorganization due to purported domination of those cases by secured creditors
in some "unfair" way, leading to a cry to "reform" the
process to restore a Edenic "balance" that actually never existed at
all.
I think the article is wrong on both counts. First, as I assume the reader has not read
it, I must explain what it says in some detail.
But to save the busier readers among you some time, here is the punch
line of my argument: All claims, secured
and unsecured, are entitled to be protected against government expropriation
under the Takings clause; the reason the topic only comes up in the context of
secured claims is that that is the only context, when dealing with an insolvent
debtor, where there is value to litigate about.
The discharge of unsecured debt in bankruptcy is indeed a taking, but often
the just compensation for the taking amounts to zero when the asset taken (the
discharged claim) is worthless, and, to the extent there is value available for
distribution on account of unsecured claims, the bankruptcy process does a
fairly reasonable job of getting that value to the holders of those
claims, mitigating any Takings claim.
Tabb;s article focuses mainly on a close reading of the major 20th century Supreme Court opinions on the limits
of the Bankruptcy Clause, which, he says, rest on a "property/contract" distinction,
that is, a secured creditor's property interest in collateral is protected by the Takings Clause to the extent of its value, while
unsecured (for which he uses the word "contract: as a proxy) claims are
not protected at all. (I will not
address what he says about older case law, which is largely irrelevant because
that era did not purport to affect secured debts via bankruptcy; in many ways,
including no concept of a going concern reorganization, and debtors' prisons,
the legal norms of the age were so different than our own that the subject was
not even dreamed of). Tabb says the "property/contract"
distinction is "false" and "with only the slightest of pushes
... collapses".
He says the distinction is "false" because
contract claims in other, non-bankruptcy contexts, have been held at the
Supreme Court level to be protected by the Takings Clause. This is correct and I won't belabor it
further.
He then goes on to devote the bulk of his attention to the
(rhetorical) question, how, then can this distinction between protecting
secured creditors under the Fifth Amendment and not protecting unsecured
creditors be sustained? Obviously he concludes
it can't, and therefore, he syllogizes, we can treat secured claims with the
same back of the hand with which we treat unsecured claims, all "for the
national good" [he actually says that].
This argument is wrong for two very obvious reasons: (1)
unsecured claims against an insolvent are often worthless, while secured claims
are often not. So, yes, unsecured claims
are "taken" when a discharge occurs, but the just compensation
required by the Takings Clause winds up being zero, because those claims are
worthless as a practical matter, and no one bothers to spend the money needed
to pursue the point as a matter of principle.
(2) When unsecured claims do have value, the bankruptcy process does a
fairly reasonable job of getting that value out to the holders of those claims,
so, again, the discharge may be a "Taking" in principle, but the
amount of the loss -- the difference between the claim amount and the value
received on account of it in the case -- which determines the amount of "just
compensation" amounts to very little in real-world dollars, and again, no
one seems to want to spend the kind of money required to establish the
principle in our legal system just as an academic matter.
So one can come up with a much more coherent explanation of
the "property/contract" distinction Tabb finds untenable: It isn't a distinction based on label, but
based on value. Both interests are
protected by the Takings clause from government expropriation to the extent of
their value, but, in the main, unsecured claims against an insolvent tend to have
no value outside of bankruptcy, whereas
secured claims have value outside of bankruptcy to the extent of the collateral's
value. That is why secured creditors
wind up receiving protection, not because they bear a magic label "property" but because
their legal rights have meaningful value
under non-bankruptcy law , while unsecured claims usually don't when the debtor
is bankrupt.
An unsecured creditor has to reduce its claim to judgment,
which may be extremely difficult (for example, in the consumer debt context,
the barring of hearsay testimony under the rules of evidence, as well as statutes
of limitations, pose real hurdles for a holder of defaulted debt to obtain a
judgment by any means other than default).
Even then, there are non-bankruptcy laws that restrict the amount that
can be collected from an individual judgment debtor, and restrict the property
that may be levied to satisfy the judgment.
There are practical obstacles to getting paid on any judgment, including
finding the debtor, finding unencumbered property, and most fundamentally, the fact
that the debtor may not make enough money to pay much of anything on the
claim. Finally, as in the business
bankruptcy context, there are usually more than just one or two unsecured
creditors and it would be difficult for any one claimant making a "Takings"
argument to prove that it would have been the one to win the "race to the
courthouse" as opposed to coming in too late to recover anything.
In the business bankruptcy context, similar hurdles exist to
realizing value on unsecured claims outside of bankruptcy. A tort claimant will need years to get to
trial, at which s/he may lose; even a winner faces appellate risks. As a practical matter, tort claimants need
settlements to get paid in any reasonable time, in or outside of
bankruptcy. A pension deficiency claim
is easy to guesstimate, but much harder to prove as a fact and, as a practical
matter, the cooperation of the debtor is necessary to expedite resolution. Trade claims are surprisingly easy to delay
payment on, including by way of disputing quality or price, except for
"critical vendors". Even for
those creditors who might get a judgment before the debtor's assets dissipated,
enforcing that judgment against a business operating in multiple states is
again a tedious and draining process requiring large legal expenses that may
not be economically recoverable. And the
"race to the courthouse" is likely to be even more congested with a
business debtor than a consumer.
So this is the point Tabb just misses: there are a large
number of non-bankruptcy reasons why unsecured claims have no value to be
compensated when they are extinguished, even though they are technically the
subject of a governmental "Taking" every time a discharge is granted.
And, when there is value available to distribute to holders
of unsecured claims, the bankruptcy process does a fairly reasonable job of
doing that. In particular, it solves for
all the unsecured creditors the collective action problem that each would face
individually. Thus, properly
administered with a view toward protecting creditors' priorities, as opposed to
indulging local business owners, it delivers a reasonable approximation of the value
that a "Takings" and "Just Compensation" suit would wind up
delivering years later. In fact, just as every discharge can be understood as a taking, so too we can see that every bankruptcy case embeds a just compensation litigation, and the Bankruptcy Code is a template for specifying the manner in which just compensation is to be figured out and paid out. And once the parties accept their respective awards consensually, or litigate them to finality, they are bound by the results and precluded by both claim and issue preclusion doctrines from relitigating the taking in the Court of Claims.
Although Tabb makes a list of arguments that might
rationalize the "property/contract" distinction (and knocks them down
one by one), this is one he just misses completely. He approaches the issue briefly, but fails to
think in terms of value and the lack thereof.
Instead, he contends that, if the unsecured creditor just gets its
ratable share of distributable value from the debtor's estate, there is
"no compensation at all" and a clear "Takings violation" -- but
then, he notes, the Supreme Court has never been troubled by that, so it must not
be a "Taking". Again, if one
ignores economic worthlessness of an unsecured claim against a no-asset estate,
as he does, that is literally correct.
But when what is "Taken" as a matter of form has no value as a
matter of economic substance, his insight becomes merely academic. The
lack of value to be compensated explains fully why no one debates the Constitutionality
of the discharge of unsecured debt outside of the academy.
Obviously, it isn't his goal to conclude that the Fifth
Amendment limits what the government can do to creditor claims that have value.
He's quite upfront about that early on, before he even begins his
argument. Citing absolutely no
empirical data, he contends that, in the new "millenium" there has
been a dramatic expansion in the power of secured creditors." As I have
shown in prior posts,
that is not true - it was well understood at the time the Bankruptcy Reform Act
of 1978 was passed that secured creditors would generally have to consent to
the plan "or the business will not be able to be reorganized." Then he contends, similarly bereft of
empirical data, that "Financing has experienced a sea change [such that] many
debtors enter bankruptcy with their assets fully encumbered." As I've shown before (see same link. and also
read the posts from January of this year), that has been a common feature of
reorganizations going back to the railroad reorganizations of our nation's
past: in the reorganization of the Denver & Rio Grande Railroad that made
multiple trips to the Supreme Court in the postwar years, all the reorganization value was
allocated to secured creditors, while the unsecured creditors and equity were wiped
out, yet neither the regulators, nor the judge presiding over the bankruptcy,
nor 7 Justices of the Court, all of whom approved the reorganization plan, had any
trouble with that fact.
He goes on in the usual horrified fashion -- continuing to
eschew empirical evidence -- to say that secured lenders are
"driving potentially viable debtors into bankruptcy" and
"Controlling secured lenders are using chapter 11 as a vehicle to
foreclose on their assets" - as if secured lenders had the ability to
decide whether their debtor stayed out of bankruptcy! Then he complains that, in these 363 sales, "important
stakeholders, bondholders, trade creditors, tort victims, employees, and shareholders,
to name but a few are excluded from any recovery but for the whims of the controlling
secured creditor" -- with no
citation but to a 1996 law review article that itself contains no empirical
data.
This is such utter nonsense: the
vast majority of 363 sales pass the debtor as a going concern to the buyer; in
them as in pretty much all prepackaged plans and even many "traditional"
chapter 11s, most trade creditors and employees usually ride right through with
little economic suffering at all. Why the
other constituencies he mentions -- bondholders and, of all things,
shareholders -- should be able to invade
the recovery of the secured creditor's collateral, Tabb conspicuously fails to
even attempt to offer a rationale.
Instead, he resorts to that tired, minimal-effort debating tactic, the
rhetorical question: "Outside of bankruptcy, the secured lender may have
considerable difficulty capturing anything above liquidation value. If the
bankruptcy process itself allows the recovery of more value, why should all of that
excess go to the secured lender?"
This approach to arguing distributional matters --
rhetorically asking one recipient how its receipt is justified -- has become a sorry
staple of debate. If one objects to a
relative distribution -- as between A & B -- as "unfair", analysis
of "unfairness" requires more than just asking "what justifies
A's receipt of the distribution?" If
it's a relative fairness issue, then you need to ask "What justifies B's
receipt of the distribution?", and then compare the two justifications
that get proffered. One can't evaluate relative
claims to a limited fund by looking at just one claim, anymore than you can
understand a team's ranking in a league's standings by asking what is its
record, and not find out the records of the other competition around it.
So here is the simple retort to Tabb's rhetorical question: Outside of bankruptcy, the unsecured creditor
may have considerable difficulty capturing anything, period. If the bankruptcy
process itself allows the recovery of more value, why should any of that excess
go to the unsecured creditor?
No comments:
Post a Comment